• No results found

A mimicking strategy exists, and can be chosen moreover so as to satisfy sup

In document Learning about analysts (sider 25-32)

ht

P(rt=buyrec|xt=0, ht, B)≤1−1−qG

qB (30)

and sup

ht P(rt=sellrec|xt=1, ht, B)≤1−1−qG

qB . (31)

Proof. Our objective will be to construct a mimicking strategy recursively, starting with t=1.

Let

P(r1=buyrec|h1, x1=1, B)=1=P(r1=sellrec|h1, x1=0, B). (32) As v1=12, then (32) implies (27) (with h1substituting ht). That (32) implies (28) and (29) is immediate.

Next suppose a strategy can be constructed such that, up to period T−1 ≥1, for all ht with tT −1, equation (27) and at least one of (28) and (29) are satisfied. Now fix a history hT; we will consider 3 cases separately.

Case 1:if

vBTqB+(1vBT)(1qB)=vTGqG+(1vTG)(1qG), let

P(rT =buyrec|hT, xT =1, B)=1=P(rT =sellrec|hT, xT =0, B).

Case 2:if instead

vBTqB+(1vBT)(1qB) < vTGqG+(1vTG)(1qG), (33) let

P(rT =buyrec|hT, xT =1, B)=1,

and

P(rT =buyrec|hT, xT =0, B)=z(hT), with z(hT)solving

vTB[qB+(1qB)z] +(1vBT)[(1qB)+qBz] =vTGqG+(1vTG)(1qG). (34) The right-hand side of (34) is bounded above by qG, and qG<1; the left-hand side evaluated at z=1 is equal to 1; lastly, the left-hand side evaluated at z=0 is strictly smaller than the right-hand side (by (33)). So z(hT)exists (and is unique, moreover).

Case 3:if

vTBqB+(1vBT)(1qB) > vTGqG+(1vTG)(1qG), (35) let

P(rT =sellrec|hT, xT =0, B)=1, and

P(rT =sellrec|hT, xT =1, B)=z(hT), with z(hT)solving

vTB[qBz+(1qB)] +(1vBT)[(1qB)z+qB] =vTG(1qG)+(1vTG)qG. (36) The right-hand side of (36) is bounded above by qG, and qG<1; the left-hand side evaluated at z=1 is equal to 1; lastly, the left-hand side evaluated at z=0 is strictly smaller than the right-hand side (by (35)). So z(hT)exists (and is unique, moreover).

It is now a simple matter to check that, irrespective of which of the cases above holds, then given hT, equation (27) and at least one of (28) and (29) are satisfied. As hT was chosen arbi-trarily, a strategy can therefore be constructed such that for all ht with t≤T, equation (27) and at least one of (28) and (29) are satisfied. But then a mimicking strategy exists, by induction.

We show next that the mimicking strategy constructed above satisfies (30). In Cases 1 and 3, P(rt=buyrec|xt=0, ht, B) =0, so (30) trivially holds. In Case 2, P(rt =buyrec|xt = 0, ht, B) =z(ht), with z(ht)solving (34). So we need to show z(ht) ≤1 −1qBqG. Notice that the left-hand side of (34) is increasing in zand, as qB12, is also increasing in vtB. The right-hand side of (34) is bounded above by qG. Since vBt ≥0, the solution to

(1qB)+qBz=qG

is thus an upper bound for z(ht). This gives z(ht) ≤1 −1qBqG. The mimicking strategy con-structed above therefore satisfies (30). That it satisfies (31) follows by symmetry. 2

Define in the remaining of the appendix, for any non-degenerate mixed strategy of the B analyst,

Lθ,t:=P(ht|V =0, θ ) P(ht|V =1, θ ) and

φθ,tr :=P(rt=r|V =0, ht, θ ) P(rt=r|V =1, ht, θ ).

Lemma 9. For any non-degenerate mixed strategy of the Banalyst and any history ht such that vGt (sellrec) =vBt (sellrec)and vGt (buyrec) =vtB(buyrec):

vBt (buyrec)vtB(sellrec)

vGt (sellrec)vtB(sellrec)= (1+φsellG,tLG,t)(φB,tsellφB,tbuy) (1+φB,tbuyLB,t)(φB,tsellφG,tsellLLG,t

B,t); (37)

vtB(buyrec)vBt (sellrec)

vGt (buyrec)vBt (buyrec)= (1+φbuyG,tLG,t)(φB,tsellφB,tbuy) (1+φB,tsellLB,t)(φbuyB,tφG,tbuyLLG,t

B,t); (38)

vtG(buyrec)vGt (sellrec)

vtG(buyrec)vBt (buyrec)= (1+φB,tbuyLB,t)(φG,tsellφbuyG,t) (1+φG,tsellLG,t)(φB,tbuyLLB,t

G,tφbuyG,t); (39)

vGt (buyrec)vBt (buyrec)

vtG(sellrec)vBt (sellrec)=(1+φG,tsellLG,t)(1+φB,tsellLB,t)(φbuyB,tφbuyG,tLLG,t

B,t) (1+φG,tbuyLG,t)(1+φB,tbuyLB,t)(φB,tsellφsellG,tLLG,t

B,t)

. (40)

Proof. Applying Bayes’ rule, vθt(r)= 1

1+φθ,tr Lθ,t.

Tedious but straightforward algebra then yields (37)–(40). 2 Lemma 10. If Bmimics G, (30)–(31)hold, and qB>12 then

infht

φsellB,tφB,tbuy>0. (41) Furthermore, if lim

t→∞nt= +∞, then

tlim→∞LB,t=0. (42)

Proof. Assume qB>12, Bmimics Gand (30)–(31) hold. Fix a history ht. Either (28) holds, or (29) does. We consider below the two possibilities.

If (28) holds then P(rt=buyrec|xt=0, ht, B) =z(ht), with z(ht)solving (34). Hence, P(rt=buyrec|V =1, ht, B)−P(rt=buyrec|V =0, ht, B)

=qB+(1qB)z(ht)− [(1qB)+qBz(ht)]

=(2qB−1)(1−z(ht))

(2qB−1)(1−qG)

qB ,

where we used (30) to obtain the final inequality.

If instead (29) holds then P(rT =sellrec|hT, xT =1, B) =z(hT), with z(ht)solving (36).

Hence,

P(rt=buyrec|V =1, ht, B)−P(rt=buyrec|V =0, ht, B)

=qB(1z(ht))(1qB)(1z(ht))

=(2qB−1)(1−z(ht))

(2qB−1)(1−qG) qB

, where we used (31) to obtain the final inequality.

As htwas chosen arbitrarily, we find infht

For the second part of the lemma, write LB,t=P(ht|V =0, B) Proof of Theorem2: Suppose Bmimics G(we are not saying at this point that such a strategy is optimal for B). Note to start with that if we were able to show that, for any t and any history ht,

mins vt(buyrec, s) > pat; (44)

maxs vt(sellrec, s) < pbt, (45)

then we would deduce (by induction) (a) Pt=ρ1) =1 for all tand ht, and also (b) mimicking Gis an optimal strategy of the B analyst. So to prove the theorem we just need to show that (44)–(45) can be made to hold for all t and all ht under the premises that B mimics G and ρt =ρ1 irrespective of t and ht. Now consider >0. As long as γG(0, 1), we can choose η >0 such that γB> γGηimplies

maxr,s |ρ1(r, s)ρ1|< ε. (46)

Our goal in the rest of the proof will be to show that if (i) Bmimics G,

(ii) (30)–(31) hold, (iii) (46) holds,

(iv) ρt=ρ1for all tand ht,

then (44)–(45) hold for all t and ht as long as we choose εsufficiently small. By virtue of the previous remarks, this will prove the theorem.

Assume qB>12, γG(0, 1)and (i)-(iv) listed above. Below, we focus on histories for which vGt (buyrec) > vtB(buyrec)and vGt (sellrec) > vBt (sellrec)(the other cases are analogous). In this case (44)–(45) hold if we can show the following inequalities:

1)vtG(buyrec)+(1ρ1+)vtB(buyrec) > pat; (47) straightforward algebra now shows that we can write (47)–(48) as

vt(buyrec)vt(sellrec) histories. Furthermore, Lemma10shows that lim

nt→+∞LB,t =0 and repeating arguments used in the proof of Theorem1establishes lim

nt→+∞LG,t= lim

nt→+∞

LG,t

LB,t =0. Hence, applying Lemmata9 and 10, positive number. As αt is bounded away from 0 and 1, choosing εsufficiently small assures that (51) holds. Repeating the steps above starting from (50) instead of (49) shows in a similar manner that (50) holds as long as we choose εsufficiently small. 2

Appendix C. Proofs of Section6

Proof of Proposition5. The method of proof is similar to the method used to prove Theorem2.

Suppose Bmimics G(we are not saying at this point that such a strategy is optimal for B). Note to start with that if we were able to show that, for any tand any history ht,

mins vt(buyrec, s) > pat; (52)

maxs vt(sellrec, s) < pbt, (53)

then we would deduce (by induction) (a) Pt=ρ1) =1 for all tand ht, and also (b) mimicking G is an optimal strategy of the B analyst. So to prove the proposition we just need to show that (52)–(53) can be made to hold for all t and all ht under the premises that Bmimics Gand ρt=ρ1irrespective of t and ht. Now consider >0. Choosing ρ <1 sufficiently large, ρ1> ρ implies

maxr,s |ρ1(r, s)ρ1|< ε. (54)

Our goal in the rest of the proof will be to show that if (i) Bmimics G,

(ii) (54) holds,

(iii) ρt=ρ1for all t and ht,

then (52)–(53) hold for all t and ht as long as we choose εsufficiently small. By virtue of the previous remarks, this will prove the proposition.

Assume (i)-(iii) listed above. Below, we focus on histories for which vGt (sellrec) >1/2 (the other cases are analogous). In this case (52)–(53) hold if we can show the following inequalities:

1)vGt (buyrec)+(1ρ1+)1 straightforward algebra now shows that we can write (55)–(56) as

ρ1

Next, denote vGt (r)the valuation conditional on θ=G, rt=rand Vt=Vt1. We can then write vGt (buyrec)vtG(sellrec)=(1z)[vGt (buyrec)vGt (sellrec)]

+z[v1G(buyrec)v1G(sellrec)].

This gives vGt (buyrec) vGt > z[v1G(buyrec) v1G(sellrec)] >0. The left-hand sides of (57) and (58) are therefore bounded below by a strictly positive number. As αt is bounded away from 0 and 1, choosing εsufficiently small assures that (57)–(58) hold. 2

Appendix. Supplementary material

Supplementary material related to this article can be found online at https://doi .org /10 .1016 / j .jet .2019 .01 .001.

References

Avery,C.,Zemsky,P.,1998.Multidimensionaluncertaintyandherdbehaviorinfinancialmarkets.Am.Econ.Rev. 88, 724–748.

Benabou,R.,Laroque,G.,1992.Usingprivilegedinformationtomanipulatemarkets:insiders,gurus,andcredibility.

Q. J.Econ. 107,921–958.

Bikhchandani,S.,Hirshleifer,D.,Welch,I.,1992.Atheoryoffads,fashion,custom,andculturalchangeasinformational cascades.J.Polit.Econ. 100,992–1026.

Brown,N.C.,Wei,K.D.,Wermers,R.,2013.Analystrecommendations,mutualfundherding,andoverreactioninstock prices.Manag.Sci. 60,1–20.

Chari,V.V.,Kehoe,P.J.,2004.Financialcrisesasherds:overturningthecritiques.J.Econ.Theory 119,128–150.

Cipriani,M.,Guarino,A.,2008.Herdbehaviorandcontagioninfinancialmarkets.B.E.J.Theor.Econ. 8.

Dasgupta,A.,Prat,A.,2008.Informationaggregationinfinancialmarketswithcareerconcerns.J.Econ.Theory 143, 83–113.

Decamps, J.-P.,Lovo,S.,2006.Informationalcascadeswithendogenousprices:Theroleofriskaversion.J.Math.

Econ. 42,109–120.

Fang,L.H.,Yasuda,A.,2014.Arestars’opinionsworthmore?Therelationbetweenanalystreputationand recommen-dationvalues.J.Financ.Serv.Res. 46,235–269.

Glosten,L.R.,Milgrom,P.R.,1985.Bid,askandtransactionpricesinaspecialistmarketwithheterogeneouslyinformed traders.J.Financ.Econ. 14,71–100.

Groysberg,B.,Healy,P.M.,Maber,D.A.,2011.Whatdrivessell-sideanalystcompensationathigh-statusinvestment banks?J.Account.Res. 49,969–1000.

Keasler,T.R.,McNeil,C.R.,2010.Madmoneystockrecommendations:marketreactionandperformance.J.Econ.

Finance 34,1–22.

Lee,I.H.,1998.Marketcrashesandinformationalavalanches.Rev.Econ.Stud. 65,741–759.

Leone,A.J.,Wu,J.S.,2007.WhatDoesItTaketoBecomeaSuperstar?EvidencefromInstitutionalInvestorRankings ofFinancialAnalysts.Workingpaper.

Loh,R.K.,Stulz,R.M.,2011.Whenareanalystrecommendationchangesinfluential?Rev.Financ.Stud. 24,593–627.

Michaely,R.,Womack,K.L.,2005.Brokeragerecommendations:stylizedcharacteristics,marketresponses,andbiases.

Adv.Behav.Finance II,389–422.

Moscarini,G.,Ottaviani,M.,Smith,L.,1998.Sociallearninginachangingworld.Econ.Theory 11,657–665.

Ottaviani,M.,Sørensen,P.N.,2006.Thestrategyofprofessionalforecasting.J.Financ.Econ. 81,441–466.

Park,A.,Sabourian,H.,2011.Herdingandcontrarianbehaviorinfinancialmarkets.Econometrica 79,973–1026.

Rüdiger,J.,Vigier,A.,2017.WhoAcquiresInformationinDealerMarkets?Workingpaper.

Sant,R.,Zaman,M.A.,1996.Marketreactiontobusinessweek‘insidewallstreet’column:aself-fulfillingprophecy.

J. Bank.Finance 20,617–643.

Scharfstein,D.S.,Stein,J.C.,1990.Herdbehaviorandinvestment.Am.Econ.Rev. 80,465–479.

Smith,L.,Sørensen,P.N.,2000.Pathologicaloutcomesofobservationallearning.Econometrica 68,371–398.

Stickel,S.E.,1995.Theanatomyoftheperformanceofbuyandsellrecommendations.Financ.Anal.J. 51,25–39.

Trueman,B.,1994.Analystforecastsandherdingbehavior.Rev.Financ.Stud. 7,97–124.

Vives,X.,1993.Howfastdorationalagentslearn?Rev.Econ.Stud. 60,329–347.

Vives,X.,1995.Thespeedofinformationrevelationinafinancialmarketmechanism.J.Econ.Theory 67,178–204.

Vives,X.,2010.InformationandLearninginMarkets:theImpactofMarketMicrostructure.PrincetonUniversityPress.

Womack,K.L.,1996.Dobrokerageanalysts’recommendationshaveinvestmentvalue?J.Finance 51,137–167.

In document Learning about analysts (sider 25-32)